Wednesday, October 31, 2012

Is Transubstantiation Defendable?


            Transubstantiation is defendable because it appeals to human reason while still keeping the double miracle of the Eucharist in tact. Thomas Aquinas, though he did not invent the term transubstantiation, is the one who greatly expounded on the virtues of this term and used Aristotelian philosophy to explain the changes that happen to the bread and wine and the changes that do not happen. This is further defendable because of the Incarnation. For centuries leading up to Aquinas, the Church used Platonism as its primary mode of explaining Church teachings philosophically. While Platonism does not reject the Incarnation, it is a philosophy that is more akin to explaining the visible world as an illusion. Aristotelian philosophy is different in this respect because it says the visible world is real. In this case, transubstantiation is seen as a fulfillment of the Incarnation on an even more tangible level.
            In the late eleventh century, there were several eucharistic controversies in the Western Church. Among the most famous, though, was Berengar of Tours’ formulation that the bread and wine at Mass did not become the Body and Blood of Christ, but was merely a “symbolic” change. After being reprimanded in 1159 and 1179, he finally capitulated and said he believed what the Church taught on this teaching. Though he was never excommunicated, only taking two oaths of fidelity, his writings on the Eucharist caused the Church to question its teachings and approach them in a more logical manner. This was indicative of the shift from a more symbolic (in the truest sense of the word) philosophy of religious teachings to the need for a more academic and logical explanation. In the mid-thirteenth century, Thomas Aquinas, a Dominican friar and professor of theology at the University of Paris, began to speak of the Eucharist using, not Platonic philosophy, as was the norm, but Aristotelian philosophy.
            Aquinas used Aristotle’s ideas of accidents and substances. Accidents were the physical appearances of bread and wine, and substances, the invisible essence of the bread and wine. Aquinas claimed that through the words of Consecration pronounced by a priest with his proper intention, and bread and wine, the bread and wine were truly transformed into the Body and Blood of Christ. The accidents, the appearance of bread and wine remained, while the substance of the bread and wine were changed into the Body and Blood. Until this time, there had not been any systematic or academic approach to the Eucharist that was satisfactory to all sides. Even though the Fourth Lateran Council in 1215 used language similar to transubstantiation, it was Aquinas who opened up a new way of looking at the Eucharist that was never done before in the history of the Eucharist.
            This metaphysical explanation of the Sacrament appeals to the Church in the West most especially because of the importance placed on the Incarnation of Christ. While the Churches in the East do hold that the bread and wine become the Body and Blood of Christ, they never felt the need to explain it in depth because of the mysterious nature of their religious ethos. This is partly due to their emphasis on the place of Easter in their liturgical rites. The West also believes in the Resurrection, obviously, but its liturgical life is centered on Christmas. This complementary dichotomy is an example of two worldviews: Platonism in the East and Aristotelian philosophy in the West. The East views the earth as a reflection of the real world of God, heaven. The liturgy in the East is more of a tearing apart of the veil between heaven and earth so that the priest can mediate the reality of heaven from God to the people, taking the people’s prayers to God. In the West, though this is not an alien concept, sees the liturgy more of a participation in Divine realities manifested through visible signs and symbols. Each liturgical ethos is non-contradictory and represents the two different strands of philosophy in the Church.
            Because of this, though, Aristotelian philosophy places more emphasis on the visible and real manifestation of Divine realities in our reality. Aristotle was a student of Plato for over twenty years, but rejected his teacher’s concepts of our visible reality participating, but not equaling, the eternal, divine realities of heaven. Plato’s use of the forms stipulates that man is a part of the earth, but merely participates in a diluted and therefore imperfect manifestation of the really real. For Aristotle, however, he believed that the earth in all its manifestations was the real world and therefore all creation was good because it was a direct participation in the divine. This reflects the Incarnation quite well because Christ became man and saved all creation, especially man, through His Passion, Death, Resurrection, and Ascension into heaven. Therefore all material of the earth can be seen as a full participation in the divine reality of the Holy Trinity, living in the love of the Trinity as it is manifested in nature.
            Transubstantiation is a defendable argument because of Aquinas’ use of Aristotelian philosophy to explain the double miracle of the Eucharist, the changing of bread and wine into the Body and Blood of Christ. The bread and wine, which man has received from the goodness of God, is offered back to God as a spotless victim. This spotless victim is Jesus Christ, the Incarnate Logos of the Father. The bread and wine are thus changed into Christ’s Body and Blood as a gift from God to man and man reciprocates by offering things of this earth where God can manifest Himself through the goodness of His creation. Transubstantiation makes sense because it explains how God is able to use any means to make Himself known to man. Even though the bread and wine are the Body and Blood of Christ substantially, accidently the bread and wine remain to speak to the anthropological need to communicating with the Creator through means man is able to comprehend. It is then that transubstantiation is defendable because it elevates visible creation to the heights of God.

2 comments:

  1. This is a good exposition.

    I may argue, however, that there is a common misconception of Aristotle (as I see it). Many seem to attribute more to Aristotle than is proper given his texts. Aquinas no doubt has influenced our view, but what you say of Aristotle is more true of Aquinas than it ever was of Aristotle.

    As such when you say "For Aristotle, however, he believed that the earth in all its manifestations was the real world and therefore all creation was good because it was a direct participation in the divine," it's not entirely true. While it is true that the material world was "really real" he also still held, as Plato did, that the 'form' of a thing was the principle of its existence and thus "real" in the truest sense.

    It wasn't until Aquinas' brilliant emphasis and exposition of 'hylomorphism' that we get this sense of a greater unity to being (i.e., form and matter).

    A minor point in the theme of this article, but I think it's always good to distinguish what Aristotle is doing as opposed to Aquinas.

    ReplyDelete
    Replies
    1. Thank you, Matt, for your clarification. What would I do without you?

      Delete